Monday, August 6, 2012

Law as Collective Agreement: A Civilizational Strategy

Studying the systems of law originating in the British Isles in their ancient, medieval, pre-modern and modern forms, an odd consistency of approach seems to emerge, in contrast with most other European systems.  That approach is the compact, the collective agreement of one part of society with another.  It reappears with strange consistency from the earliest recorded laws to the present day.

The Brehon laws of ancient Ireland, which were remarkable in many ways for their humanity and moderation in an era characterised elsewhere in Europe by capital punishment for the most trivial of crimes and judicial procedure based upon the ordeal, operated entirely on this principle.  When Ireland had High Kings, they would call a feis or gathering of all the educated people and leaders of the country every three years to discuss matters of law.  The promulgation of laws was not a monopoly of kings; in order to pass a law, the king had to call together a council of at least nine people of particular stations, including a teacher of law, a teacher of history, a bard, clergymen and so on.  The king himself was bound by certain specific laws.  The laws themselves were essentially the product of and guide to the negotiations of the different parts of society with each other, each part having certain rights. 

That this process of negotiation was ongoing can be seen in the advancement of women’s rights in recorded laws.  Despite a low status in the earlier law tracts, by the late "Dark Ages," Irish women were the freest in Europe, able to divorce as well as to own, accumulate and transmit property.  The very legal process itself took on the aspect of a negotiation mediated by the jurist, and the consequences for even serious crimes were often shockingly lenient in modern eyes.  The process of negotiation within the society over time leant the Irish laws a remarkable humanity, mirrored in the other Celtic law systems for which we have evidence, and arguably in the Anglo-Saxon laws of Alfred the Great, who, likely due to centuries of Irish missionising, seems to have adopted many similar legal concepts. 

The laws of Norman England were by far the darkest in British history, reverting to trial by ordeal, not to mention hanging for offenses ranging from adultery to petty theft to killing the King’s game.  The nobility and the Church had their own courts, and the power of life and death over their serfs.  Of the legal systems in play, the king’s law was, for the average person, perhaps the least significant.

Rivalry between kings and nobles led to the collective agreement (soon broken) known as Magna Carta, and later to a particularly interesting rebellion led Simon de Montfort, Earl of Leicester.  Simon, whose anniversary of death was this past week, was responsible the first directly-elected Parliament, also the first which had substantial rights of government and in which commoners had a substantial role, and was one of the first pioneers of democracy in England.  Simon was one of the first to see beyond the rights of his own class and to try for a constitution beneficial to the nation writ large.

It was around this time (the 13th Century) that the English monarchy smartened up.  Royal law had enjoyed minimal presence in the Shires, and to lend it credibility, the idea of indictment, and later trial, by a jury of freemen was introduced.  The former kind of jury seems to have been a significant influence on the abandonment of the ordeal system, and there are records of accused persons throwing themselves "on the verdict of the country" before the trial jury was introduced.  The free farmers and the burgers of the growing charter boroughs, the minority of the non-noble population directly affected by the King’s law, would henceforth be judged firstly by the fair mind of the community (your mileage may vary) and secondly by the distillation of the fair mind of the law (ditto), embodied in the precedents of the Common Law.  The power of the jury was of great help to the non-noble classes in resisting the nobility on certain points, such as the noble monopoly on game.  A jury composed of poachers and those sympathetic to poachers was unlikely to uphold an unfair noble privilege when one of their peers was caught.

The negotiations and arguments around the role of the jury have a fascinating history, (almost every argument made against juries today is at least four hundred years old), with many vicissitudes, but it was in the early modern period, with the disappearance of serfdom, an educated middle class and juries willing and able to defy the letter of the law to preserve the spirit of justice that the jury came into its own.  Notably in the trials of Quakers, juries refused to convict and withstood judicial sanctions including fines and imprisonment for it.  It was this issue which ultimately forced the law to fully recognise the right of jury nullification, which had in practice been occurring since the dawn of the jury trial.  The fair mind of the (property-owning male) community could overturn unjust laws, such as those restricting the freedom of worship.

English history is often read as a process of negotiation between the classes: the king and the nobility, the lower nobility and the higher, the nobility and the middle class, and so on.  The markers of these negotiations- Magna Carta, the English Revolution, the Restoration, the Glorious Revolution, th 19th Century reforms, the extensions of the franchise, each represent a renegotiation of the rights and privileges of particular classes and of the monarchy.  The negotiated nature of law is inherent in the Westminster system, as every written law is a signed agreement between the monarch and the representatives of the people.  In that way, the monarch gradually became the embodiment and guarantor of the constitution, rather than a lawgiver, in a way that gives the whole system an incredible resilience. 

The intervals between the Saxon and Danish invasions, the Norman Conquest in 1066 and the reforms of the 19th Century in Britain can be read as a gradual amelioration of the legal concepts brought by the invaders, through the extension of the right of collective bargaining to ever-wider portions of society.  It is from this process that our most treasured legal principles, from Habeas Corpus to the presumption of innocence to the right to legal council, gradually emerged. 

Even so, it is striking that until the parliamentary and legal reforms of the 19th Century and the extensions of the franchise to most of the population, the system seems scarcely recognisable.  Until that time, we see mainly a sort of theatre of justice, quick trials conducted with private prosecution and easily decided by the prejudices of judge and jury, and culminating too often in the spectacle of a public hanging for offenses ranging from the trivial to the unrecognisable.  Only when women and the lower classes were included in the conversation did the law start to become more human and less a system for the defence of the upper-class male and his property, social and sexual rights.

Despite all its disadvantages- a slow learning curve and tendency to periodically forget the lessons of the past- the principle of collective agreement as the basis for law is the irreplaceable foundation of modern democracy.  In place of a lawgiver and a rigid code of penalties policed by force, this ideal places the monarch and the people, the rich and the poor, the state and the citizen, and each section of society with every other, in negotiation and seeks a credible collective arrangement.  The system is admittedly imperfect.  But it does not stand for perfection.  It stands for humanity and legitimacy, and imposes a series of time-tested speed bumps on any one force of state or society running roughshod over any other.  That is why, whenever I read a comment by police or crown lawyers decrying the fact that juries, unlike judges, are not inclined to take police testimony uncritically and are likely to demand a high standard of proof (I can produce studies on both points), I think, “Great!  An example of the system working!”

None of this is to say that the law in the UK, here in Canada or down south in the US is anywhere close to working right.  Trivial offenses fill dockets and prisons while violent criminals are paroled early to make room.  Political priorities and not the safety of the people apportion the resources of the law and the police.  The right to speedy trial is a sick joke, as is the right to effective representation.  Laws are tangled, criminally lengthy and totally inaccessible to the citizen.  The bar and the judiciary are self-selecting interest groups with no interest in cleaning up the situation.  The police in many places are disturbingly occupied with questions of public order and paramilitary training and disturbingly unoccupied with community relations and catching serious criminals, not to mention the training and behaviours of their own officers which too often bring the administration of justice into disrepute.  Corporate and white-collar crime is remarkably unchecked, while small-time street crooks are the focus of every political campaign. 

As we ponder these and other problems, the subjects for the next great renegotiation of the law and the social compact, we the people could do worse than remember this heritage of collective negotiation, its lessons, and the ways in which it empowers us.  The law and the legal system stands or falls on the legitimacy we give it.  If we refuse to put up with the status quo- well, that is what workers and women did in the 19th Century, the slave-trade abolitionists before that and the jury and its supporters before that.  That is how the social compact and the laws which embody it get renegotiated in a democratic society.

No comments:

Post a Comment